Sand Opera
Lenten Journey Day 4
Isaiah
58
Thus
says the LORD:
If you remove from your midst oppression,
false accusation and malicious speech;
If you bestow your bread on the hungry
and satisfy the afflicted;
Then light shall rise for you in the darkness,
and the gloom shall become for you like midday…
If you remove from your midst oppression,
false accusation and malicious speech;
If you bestow your bread on the hungry
and satisfy the afflicted;
Then light shall rise for you in the darkness,
and the gloom shall become for you like midday…
(echo/ex) from SAND OPERA |
Note:
As I re-read
this poem today, I’m reminded of the dual difficulty it presents:
that of telling traumatic stories, and of listening to them. The Iraqi who
testified to what happened says that he had nothing to gain materially from
telling this story, and that he wasn’t even supposed to tell it, but he tells
it anyway, even as it returns him to the experience of total humiliation. His
voice is difficult to hear because to hear it means that we enter into his experience
of suffocating debasement. It also necessitates that we recognize that those
who did this to him were Americans. In some strange way, we are the indirect
authors of his pain. In today’s readings, Isaiah exhorts us to remove
oppression from our midst, but the layers that separate us from this man are so
manifold, so visibly invisible, it is difficult to know precisely how.
Two simple ways
to begin this process of conscientization. One way is to remember, to remember
something that has not been included our collective memory, but nonetheless involves
us. For example, today is the twenty-fifth anniversary of the Al
Amiriyah Attack, in which 400 Iraqi civilians (mostly women and children) in
a Baghdad bomb shelter were killed by U.S. missile attacks during the Persian
Gulf War. Dima Yassine was ten minutes from the bombing, and could smell the
burned flesh for days afterward. http://www.jadaliyya.com/pages/index/23839/resisting-amnesia_twenty-five-years-after-the-al-a
What would it
mean to remember Al Amiriyah—or The Move bombing in Philadelphia, for example—as
clearly as the San Bernadino attacks or even 9/11?
The second way,
specifically related to the content of this poem, is to scrutinize current U.S.
policy regarding interrogation. My colleague, the ethicist Paul Lauritzen,
wrote a deeply thoughtful examination of U.S. policies of interrogation, particularly
the Bush Administration’s employment of the Orwellian-sounding “enhanced
interrogation.” In The Ethics of Interrogation, Lauritzen attempts to create a moral
framework to guide U.S. interrogation policy, differentiating between coercive
interrogation (which he believes is legal and moral) and abusive interrogation.
The key, for him, regards the question of whether interrogation acknowledges
and maintains the dignity of the one under interrogation. One might hasten to
add, with Isaiah in mind, the interrogator’s own potential loss of dignity.
Here it is
useful to be concrete. Suppose we turn to the techniques set out in Army Field
Manual 34-52, the 1992 Army document that spells out guidelines for
“intelligence interrogation” and to the ten enhanced interrogation techniques
that the classified Bybee memorandum addressed in August 2002. How should these
various techniques be classified? We can
begin with FM 34-52. The manual covers interrogation in great detail, with
chapters on everything from the general mission of military intelligence units
and the structure of such units to the handling of documents produced through
intelligence operations, including interrogation. Chapter three of the manual
covers the actual techniques of interrogation. It identifies roughly a dozen
general interrogation strategies, with some variations within each category. The
categories are: direct, incentive, emotional, fear, pride and ego, futility, we
know all, file and dossier, establish your identity, repetition, rapid fire,
silence, and change of scene.
The coercive
nature of all interrogation can be seen in the fact that even in the most
innocuous of these techniques, namely, a direct approach in which the
interrogator simply asks for the information he wants, the subject being
interrogated is powerless and vulnerable. The detainee does not necessarily
know where he is; he does not know what will happen if he refuses to answer;
and even if he answers questions truthfully, he may not be believed. Nevertheless,
not all techniques are the same. Asking a detainee a direct question is very
different from what the manual refers to as a “Fear-Up (Harsh)” approach. According
to the manual, “in this [Fear-Up (Harsh)] approach, the interrogator behaves in
an overpowering manner with a loud and threatening voice. The interrogator may
even feel the need to throw objects across the room to heighten the source’s
implanted feelings of fear . . . This technique is to convince the source he
does indeed have something to fear; that he has no option but to cooperate.”
The fact that
questioning a detainee is coercive and may be harsh, however, does not mean it
is morally or legally prohibited. Indeed, all the techniques set out in FM
34-52 are approved by the military, in part because they do not violate Geneva
Conventions or the Uniform Code of Military Justice. The Preface to the manual
is clear about the necessity of restraint. “These principles and techniques of
interrogation,” the manual reads, “are to be used within the constraints
established by the following”:
·
The Uniform Code of Military Justice (UCMJ)
·
Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Wounded and
Sick in Armed Forces in the Field of August 12, 1949, hereinafter referred to
as GWS
·
Geneva Convention Relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of
War of August 12, 1949, hereinafter referred to as GPW
·
Geneva Convention Relative to the Protection of Civilian
Persons in Time of War of August 12, 1949, hereinafter referred to as GC.
Article three,
which is common to all three of these Conventions, provides an indication of
the basis upon which interrogations are to be judged. It reads:
(1) Persons taking no
active part in the hostilities, including members of armed forces who have laid
down their arms and those placed 'hors de combat' by sickness, wounds,
detention, or any other cause, shall in all circumstances be treated humanely,
without any adverse distinction founded on race, colour, religion or faith,
sex, birth or wealth, or any other similar criteria. To this end, the following
acts are and shall remain prohibited at any time and in any place whatsoever
with respect to the above-mentioned persons: (a) violence to life and person,
in particular murder of all kinds, mutilation, cruel treatment and torture; (b)
taking of hostages; (c) outrages upon personal dignity, in particular
humiliating and degrading treatment; (d) the passing of sentences and the
carrying out of executions without previous judgment pronounced by a regularly
constituted court, affording all the judicial guarantees which are recognized
as indispensable by civilized peoples.
From this
and other articles in the conventions, it is clear that the standard that is to
guide the treatment of prisoners is one that safeguards the dignity and
humanity of prisoners. Prisoners should not be degraded; they should not be
treated cruelly; and they should not be physically or emotionally abused.
--Paul Lauritzen is Professor of Religious
Ethics at John Carroll University in Cleveland. He is the author or editor of 5
books, including The
Ethics of Interrogation (2013), and has published extensively on issues in
bioethics, human rights, and religious ethics. He is the past coeditor of the
Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics and is currently an associate editor
with the Journal of Religious Ethics.
No comments:
Post a Comment